The Road to Serfdom
Published in 1944
Friedrich Hayek
Friedrich Hayek (1899-1992) was an Austrian-British economist known for his defense of classical liberalism and his critiques of central planning. The Road to Serfdom, his seminal work, warns about the dangers of socialism and emphasizes the importance of competition in preserving liberty.
Chapters
Chapter | Summary |
---|---|
Chapter 1: The Abandoned Road | Summary |
Chapter 2: The Great Utopia | Summary |
Chapter 3: Individualism and Collectivism | Summary |
Chapter 4: The "Inevitability" of Planning | Summary |
Chapter 5: Planning and Democracy | Summary |
Chapter 6: Planning and the Rule of Law | Summary |
Chapter 7: Economic Control and Totalitarianism | Summary |
Chapter 8: Who, whom? | Summary |
Chapter 9: Security and Freedom | Summary |
Chapter 10: Why the Worst Get on Top | Summary |
Chapter 11: The End of Truth | Summary |
Chapter 12: The Socialist Roots of Naziism | Summary |
Chapter 13: The Totalitarians in Our Midst | Summary |
Chapter 14: Material Conditions and the Ideal Ends | Summary |
Chapter 15: The Prospects of International Order | Summary |
Chapter 16: Conclusion | Summary |
The Meaning of Socialism
"At the time I wrote, socialism meant unambiguously the nationalization of the means of production and the central economic planning which this made possible and necessary." (p. 54)
"It may mean, and is often used to describe, merely the ideals of social justice, greater equality, and security, which are the ultimate aims of socialism. But it means also the particular method by which most socialists hope to attain these ends and which many competent people regard as the only methods by which they can be fully and quickly attained. In this sense socialism means the abolition of private enterprise, of private ownership of the means of production, and the creation of a system of "planned economy" in which the entrepreneur working for profit is replaced by a central planning body." (p. 83)
"What in effect unties the socialists of the Left and the Right is this common hostility to competition and their common desire to replace it by a directed economy." (p. 88)
At the time Friedrich Hayek originally wrote The Road to Serfdom, socalism referred to the nationalization of the means of production, the abolition private enterprise, and the replacement of competition with a directed economy via central economic planning. Additionally, it could be used by some to represent merely the ideals of social justice, greater equality, and security, without referring to the previously listed methods of implementing those ideals.
"... socialism has come to mean chiefly the extensive redistrubtion of incomes through taxation and the institutions of the welfare state. In the latter kind of socialism the effects I discuss in this book are brought about more slowly, indirectly, and imperfectly." (p. 54)
Here Hayek explains how the meaning of socialism had changed from when he originally wrote the book in 1944, to when he wrote a new preface in 1976. While Hayek recognizes that his book adresses socialism as its earlier definiton, he believes that the consequences of socialism as he originally stated them will still be brought about by the new meaning of socialism, albeit in a slower, less direct, and inferior manner.
The Meaning of Planning
""Planning" owes its popularity largely to the fact that everybody desires, of course, that we should handle our common problems as rationally as possible and that, in so doing, we should use as much foresight as we can command. [...] But it is not in this sense that our enthisiasts for a planned society now employ this term[...]." (p. 85)
"What our planners demand is a central direction of all economic activity according to a single plan, laying down how the resources of society should be "consciously directed" to serve particular ends in a definite way." (p. 85)
Collectivism & Individualism
"The common features of all collectivist systems may be described, in a phrase ever dear to socialists of all schools, as the deliberate organization of the labors of society for a definite social goal. That our present society lacks such "conscious" direction toward a single aim, that its activities are guided by the whims and fancies of irresponsible individuals, has always been one of the main complaints of its socialist critics." (p. 100)
"The various kinds of collectivism, communism, fascism, etc., differ among themselves in the nature of the goal toward which they want to direct the efforts of society. But they all differ from liberalism and individualism in wanting to organize the whole of society and all its resources for a unitary end and in refusing to recognize autonomous spheres in which the ends of the individuals are supreme. In short, they are totalitarian in the true sense of this new word which we have adopted to describe the unexpected but nevertheless inseparable manifestations of what in theory we call collectivism." (p. 100)
"Liberalism" vs "Conservatism"
"I use throughout the term "liberal" in the original, nineteenth-century sense in which it is still current in Britain. In current American usage it often means very nearly the opposite of this. It has been part of the camouflage of leftish movements in this country, helped by the muddleheadedness of many who really believe in liberty, that "liberal" has come to mean the advocacy of almost every kind of government control." (p. 45)
First and foremost, the reader needs to recognize the distinction between the definition of liberalism as Hayek refers to it, and the definition as which it has come to be more commonly known. The definition of Liberalism that Hayek refers to is that of its most common meaning in the 19th century, that of which we refer to as classical liberalism today. On Liberty by John Stewart Mill covers this meaning in more detail. Liberalism today (and by 1956, when Hayek wrote a new foreword), has come to represent leftish movements. Hayek argues that liberalism has come to mean the opposite of its 19th century meaning, because leftish movements advocate for nearly every kind of government control.
"... true liberalism is still distinct from conservatism, and there is danger in the two being confused. Conservatism, though a necessary element in any stable society, is not a social program; in its paternalistic, nationalistic, and power-adoring tendencies it is often closer to socialism than true liberalism; and with its traditionalistic, anti-intellectual, and often mystical propensities it will never, except in short perioids of disillusionment, appeal to the young and all those others who believe that some changes are desirable if this world is to become a better place. A conservative movement, by its very nature, is bound to be a defender of established privilege and to lean on the power of government for the protection of privilege. The essence of the liberal position, however, is the denial of all privilege, if privilege is understood in its proper and original meaning of the state granting and protecting rights to some which are not available on equal terms to others." (p. 46)
Though Hayek bashes liberalism, or leftism, he makes no allegiance to conservatism either. Hayek does not endevour to clearly define what liberalism (leftism) or conservatism means, but seems to have brought up the issue to clear up the confusion around the term liberalism, and to warn the reader about conflating conservatism with classical liberalism.
The Rule of Law
"The distinction we have drawn before between the creation of a permanent framework of laws within which the productive activity is guided by individual decisions and the direction of economic activity by a central authority is thus really a particular case of the more general distinction between the Rule of Law and arbitrary government. Under the first the government confines itself to fixing rules determining the conditions under which the available resources may be used, leaving to the individuals the decision for what ends they are to be used. Under the second the government directs the use of the means of production to particular ends." (p. 113)
"To produce the same result for different people, it is necessary to treat them differently. To give different people the same objective opportunities is not to give them the same subjective chance. It cannot be denied that the Rule of Law produces economic inequality-all that can be claimed for it is that this inequality is not designed to affect particular people in a particular way." (p. 117)
"The Rule of Law thus implies limits to the scope of legislation: it restricts it to the kind of general rules known as formal law and excludes legislation either directly aimed at particular people or at enabling anybody to use the coercive power of the state for the purpose of such discrimination." (p. 120)
Essentially, the Rule of Law means that the government creates laws in advance that apply to general situations, which restricts its own power and allows for people to plan to avoid violating the laws. The lack of the Rule of Law would allow governments to create laws in specific situations or in response to specific things, and to let them direct what is done by people. Laws would be created on much more of an ad hoc basis.
"To say that in a planned society the Rule of Law cannot hold is, therefore, not to say that the actions of the government will not be legal or that such a society will necessarily be lawless. It means only that the use of the government's coercive powers will no longer be limited and determined by pre-established rules" (p. 119)
Security
"It will be well to contrast at the outset the two kinds of security: the limited one, which can be achieved for all, and which is therefore no privilege but a legitimate object of desire; and absolute security, which in a free society cannot be achieved for all and which ought not to be given as a privilege[...]. These two kinds of security are, first, security against severe physical privation, the certainty of a given minimum of sustenance for all; and, second, the security of a given standard of life, or the relative position which one person or group enjoys compared with others; or, as we may put it briefly, the security of the particular income a person is thought to deserve." (p. 147)
Fascism & National Socialism
"There is a great deal of truth in the often heard statement that fascism and National Socialism are a sort of middle-class socialism— only that in Italy and Germany the supporters of these new movements were economically hardly a middle class any longer. It was to a large extent a revolt of a new underprivileged class against the labor aristocracy which the industrial labor movement had created." (p. 144)